Skip navigation
Please use this identifier to cite or link to this item: http://arks.princeton.edu/ark:/88435/dsp01k0698765f
Full metadata record
DC FieldValueLanguage
dc.contributor.advisorCooper, John M.en_US
dc.contributor.authorSegev, Moren_US
dc.contributor.otherPhilosophy Departmenten_US
dc.date.accessioned2014-06-05T19:46:01Z-
dc.date.available2018-06-05T08:06:38Z-
dc.date.issued2014en_US
dc.identifier.urihttp://arks.princeton.edu/ark:/88435/dsp01k0698765f-
dc.description.abstractAristotle criticizes the content of Greek religion severely. He thinks that it is demonstrably false. Surprisingly, however, he also holds that traditional religion and its institutions are necessary if any city, including the ideal city he describes in <italic>Politics</italic> VII-VIII, is to exist and thrive. My dissertation aims to provide, for the first time, a coherent account of the socio-political role Aristotle attributes to traditional religion despite his rejection of its content. In the <italic>De philosophia</italic>, a dialogue surviving only in fragmentary quotations and paraphrases, Aristotle compares the gods of traditional religion to Platonic Forms. He dismisses both as fictional entities - the products of an erroneous inference from the obvious and universally agreed existence of certain objects to the existence of eternal beings causing them and bearing similar properties. Yet, in the same work, Aristotle attributes to religious practices the capacity to produce emotional states that are conducive to learning. This view anticipates his account of the role of institutionalized traditional religion in his extant corpus. According to his theory there, religion is necessary because it prepares the ground for what he considers the pinnacle of human endeavor: attaining the knowledge of first philosophy, whose objects are real beings worthy of being called gods, viz. the unmoved movers of the heavens. Religion performs that function by exposing citizens to the traditional depictions of divinity. These, in turn, generate in the citizens with the right potential the sense of 'wonder' (<italic>thaumazein</italic>) about gods that guides them from such mythological conceptions to an inquiry into the nature of the true god(s) of Aristotle's <italic>Metaphysics</italic>. In addition, since the anthropomorphic gods partake of the definitions of both 'human being' and 'god,' wondering about their nature can initiate an inquiry into the relation between gods and humans. Both kinds of inquiry are essential for getting as close as humanly possible to the condition of the divine, and the role of traditional religion in achieving that goal, which Aristotle considers the highest human aspiration, is therefore immensely significant, both for the individual happiness of any citizen and for the flourishing of the city.en_US
dc.language.isoenen_US
dc.publisherPrinceton, NJ : Princeton Universityen_US
dc.relation.isformatofThe Mudd Manuscript Library retains one bound copy of each dissertation. Search for these copies in the <a href=http://catalog.princeton.edu> library's main catalog </a>en_US
dc.subjectAnthropomorphismen_US
dc.subjectAristotleen_US
dc.subjectGodsen_US
dc.subjectPolitical functionen_US
dc.subjectReligionen_US
dc.subjectTraditional religionen_US
dc.subject.classificationPhilosophyen_US
dc.subject.classificationClassical studiesen_US
dc.subject.classificationPhilosophy of Religionen_US
dc.titleThe Role of Traditional Religion in Aristotleen_US
dc.typeAcademic dissertations (Ph.D.)en_US
pu.projectgrantnumber690-2143en_US
pu.embargo.terms2018-06-05en_US
Appears in Collections:Philosophy

Files in This Item:
File Description SizeFormat 
Segev_princeton_0181D_10935.pdf713.12 kBAdobe PDFView/Download


Items in Dataspace are protected by copyright, with all rights reserved, unless otherwise indicated.