Skip navigation
Please use this identifier to cite or link to this item: http://arks.princeton.edu/ark:/88435/dsp018s45q8821
Full metadata record
DC FieldValueLanguage
dc.contributor.advisorMacedo, Stephenen_US
dc.contributor.advisorSinger, Peteren_US
dc.contributor.authorFlanigan, Jessicaen_US
dc.contributor.otherPolitics Departmenten_US
dc.date.accessioned2012-11-15T23:55:17Z-
dc.date.available2012-11-15T23:55:17Z-
dc.date.issued2012en_US
dc.identifier.urihttp://arks.princeton.edu/ark:/88435/dsp018s45q8821-
dc.description.abstractI argue that citizens have rights of self-medication, and that prohibitive pharmaceutical regulations are therefore unjust. Pharmaceuticals are among the most important consumer goods we will ever purchase. Yet despite, or perhaps because of their importance, pharmaceuticals are heavily regulated in ways that other consumer goods are not: through premarket approval requirements and prescription drug systems. I begin with a historical overview of pharmaceutical regulation (Ch. 1). I then show that prohibitive pharmaceutical polices cause death and suffering by discouraging innovation and by preventing patients from accessing beneficial and lifesaving drugs (Ch. 2). Indeed, adopting less prohibitive pharmaceutical policies is one way that a liberal society might promote public health. (Ch. 3) I then argue that liberal principles are often incompatible with pharmaceutical paternalism (Ch. 4). Further, seriously ill patients have rights of medical self-defense that entail rights to use unapproved drugs (Ch. 5). People also have rights to use drugs to end their lives even if they are not sick or disabled. (Ch. 6) Together, these arguments justify conditional rights of self-medication and call for extensive reforms to the current system of regulation. I then argue that the same principles of anti-paternalism that are used to justify the doctrine of informed consent also justify unconditional rights of self-medication (Ch. 7). Governments that enforce prohibitive pharmaceutical regulations are morally culpable for the harms and wrongful deaths that are caused thereby (Ch. 8). Even though citizens overwhelmingly support prohibitive policies, prohibitions themselves do not serve the public interest (Ch. 9). To close, I propose several institutional reforms including the legalization of almost all pharmaceuticals and changes to medical practice (Ch. 10). I also discuss some circumstances where limits on self-medication are justified (Ch. 11). More generally, this is an argument for more extensive rights against paternalistic interference in medicine, and a call to end deadly and ineffective pharmaceutical regulations. All governments are unjust insofar as they restrict patients' access to therapeutic medicine. Institutional protections for rights of self-medication aim to remedy this everyday injustice, and in so doing, save lives and empower patients.en_US
dc.language.isoenen_US
dc.publisherPrinceton, NJ : Princeton Universityen_US
dc.relation.isformatofThe Mudd Manuscript Library retains one bound copy of each dissertation. Search for these copies in the <a href=http://catalog.princeton.edu> library's main catalog </a>en_US
dc.subjectClinical Trialsen_US
dc.subjectFDAen_US
dc.subjectHealth Careen_US
dc.subjectPaternalismen_US
dc.subjectPharmaceuticalsen_US
dc.subjectPrescription drugsen_US
dc.subject.classificationMedical ethicsen_US
dc.subject.classificationEthicsen_US
dc.subject.classificationPhilosophyen_US
dc.titleLiberal Medicineen_US
dc.typeAcademic dissertations (Ph.D.)en_US
pu.projectgrantnumber690-2143en_US
Appears in Collections:Politics

Files in This Item:
File Description SizeFormat 
Flanigan_princeton_0181D_10343.pdf1.97 MBAdobe PDFView/Download


Items in Dataspace are protected by copyright, with all rights reserved, unless otherwise indicated.